Nearly sufficient statistics
How about “Sufficient sufficiency”? — is that taken?
March 13, 2018 — January 14, 2019
🏗
I’m working through a small realisation, for my own interest, which has been helpful in my understanding of variational Bayes; specifically relating it to non-Bayes variational inference. Also sequential monte carlo.
NB: I have shelved this for now. Worked through my ideas, discovered that I was more-or-less reinventing rate-distortion theory and decided not to chase it. I may return later for pedagogic purposes.
By starting from the idea of sufficient statistics, we come to the idea of variational inference in a natural way, via some other interesting stopovers.
Consider the Bayes filtering setup. We have some system whose parameters we wish to estimate, and we have many experiments done upon that system, throughout time. We would like to update our understanding of that system, using the experiments’ data. Possibly the system is changing, possibly it’s not changing. Either way (or both ways) there is a computational challenge.
(Or it’s not changing, but our model is increasing in size as we gain more data about it. How to handle this case?)
We would like the hypothesis updating to happen in a compact way, where we can do inference without keeping the whole data-set about, but rather use some summary statistics. With exponential family models this is trivial to do; just use conjugate updates and you are done. With models where compactness would be more useful, say, big data and big models without conjugate updates, it’s not clear how we can do this exactly.
See also mixture models, probabilistic deep learning, directed graphical models, other probability metrics.
Possibly related: Related, but not quite the same, learning summary statistics or Data summarisation via inducing sets or coresets. That latter does not reduce the dimension of the data, but the size of the data set. Bounded Memory Learning? To mention: Pitman—Koopman—Darmois theorem. Other fun keywords: rate distortion, sufficient statistic paradox…
1 Sufficient statistics in exponential families
Let’s start with sufficient statistics in exponential families, which, for reasons of historical pedagogy, are the Garden of Eden of Inference. (the Garden of Edenference for short.) I suspect that deep in their hearts, all statisticians regard themselves as prodigal exiles from the exponential family, and long for the innocence of that Garden of Edenference.
Informally, here’s what’s going on with the inference problems involving sufficient statistics. We are interested in estimating some parameter of inference, \(\theta\) using realisations \(x\) of some random process \(X\sim \mathbb{P}(x|\theta).\)
Then \(T(x)\) is a sufficient statistic for \(\theta\) iff \[\mathbb{P}(x|T(x),\theta)= \mathbb{P}(x|T(x)).\] That is, our inference about \(\theta\) depends on the data only through the sufficient statistic.
(mention size of sufficient statistic)
Fisher—Neyman factorization theorem \[ \mathbb{P}(x;\theta)=h(x)g(T(x);\theta) \]
Famously, Maximum Likelihood estimators of exponential family models are highly compressible, in that these have sufficient statistics — these are low-dimensional functions of the data which characterise all the information in the complete data, with respect to the parameter estimates. Many models and data sets and estimation methods do not have this feature, even parametric models with very few parameters.
This can be a PITA when your data is very big and you wish to get benefit from that, and yet you can’t fit the data in memory; The question then arises — when can I do better? Can I find a “nearly sufficient” statistic, which is smaller than my data and yet does not worsen my error substantially? Can I quantify this nearness to the original?