Scientific institutions and mechanisms

Descriptive and normative

August 24, 2021 — April 8, 2024

adaptive
bounded compute
collective knowledge
distributed
economics
how do science
incentive mechanisms
institutions
learning
mind
networks
sociology
standards
swarm
Figure 1

On heuristic mechanism and institutional design for communities of scientific practice for the enrichment of the common property resource that is human knowledge. How do diverse underfunded teams manage to advance truth with their weird prestige economy despite the many pitfalls of publication filters and such? What is effective in designing communities, practice and social norms? Both of scientific insiders and outsiders? How much communication is too much? How much iconoclasm is right to defeat groupthink and foster the spread of good ideas? At an individual level we might wonder about soft methodology. What is the profit model?

A place to file questions like this, in other words (O’Connor and Wu 2021):

Diversity of practice is widely recognized as crucial to scientific progress. If all scientists perform the same tests in their research, they might miss important insights that other tests would yield. If all scientists adhere to the same theories, they might fail to explore other options which, in turn, might be superior. But the mechanisms that lead to this sort of diversity can also generate epistemic harms when scientific communities fail to reach swift consensus on successful theories. In this paper, we draw on extant literature using network models to investigate diversity in science. We evaluate different mechanisms from the modeling literature that can promote transient diversity of practice, keeping in mind ethical and practical constraints posed by real epistemic communities. We ask: what are the best ways to promote the right amount of diversity of practice in such communities?

Figure 2

1 Institution design

  • Accelerating science through evolvable institutions

    The biggest red flag is with our institutions of science. Institutions affect all the other factors, especially the management of money and talent. And today, many in the metascience community have concerns about our institutions. Common criticisms include:

    • Speed. It can easily take 12–18 months to get a grant (if you’re lucky)
    • Overhead. Researchers typically spend 30–50% of their time on grants
    • Patience. Researchers feel they need to show results regularly and can’t pursue a path that might take many years to get to an outcome
    • Risk tolerance. Grant funding favors conservative, incremental proposals rather than bold, “high-risk, high-reward” programs (despite efforts to the contrary)
    • Consensus. A field can converge on a hypothesis and prune alternate branches of study too quickly
    • Researcher age. The trend over time is for grant money to go to older, more established researchers
    • Freedom. Scientists lack the freedom to direct their research fully autonomously; grant funding has too many strings attached

    Now, as a former tech founder, I can’t help but notice that most of these problems seem much alleviated in the world of for-profit VC funding. Raising VC money is relatively quick (typically a round comes together in a few months rather than a year or more). As a founder/CEO, I spent about 10–15% of my time fundraising, not 30–50%. VCs make bold bets, actively seek contrarian positions, and back young upstarts. They mostly give founders autonomy, perhaps taking a board seat for governance, and only firing the CEO for very bad performance. (The only concern listed above that startup founders might also complain about is patience: if your money runs out, you’d better have progress to show for it, or you’re going to have a bad time raising the next round.)

    I don’t think the VC world does better on these points because VCs are smarter, wiser, or better people than science funders—they’re not. Rather, VCs:

    • Compete for deals (and really don’t want to miss good deals)
    • Succeed or fail in the long run based on the performance of their portfolio
    • See those outcomes within a matter of ~5–10 years

    In short, VCs are subject to evolutionary pressure. They can’t get stuck in obviously bad equilibria because if they do they will get out-competed and lose market power.

  • Focused Research Organizations: A New Model for Scientific Research

  • Focused Research Organizations to Accelerate Science, Technology, and Medicine

  • A Guide to DeSci, the Latest Web3 Movement

  • The Overedge Catalog: The Future of Research Organizations

    Research organizations and institutions often are shoehorned into a set of well-established categories: universities, public companies, tech startups, and certain types of non-profits, such as think tanks. But there is the need for innovation here, particularly when it comes to encouraging the development of new ideas and the ability to operate on long timescales. We need new types of research organizations.

    In cartography, most maps are bound by the straight lines at their borders. But occasionally, there are parts of the map that don’t quite fit. They bleed over the edge and yet still cry out for being included in a map. These are the overedges. The Overedge Catalog is devoted to collecting the intriguing new types of organizations and institutions that lie at the intersection of the worlds of research and academia, non-profits, and tech startups

  • Labs · Patrick Collison

  • Organizations with structures worth learning from

2 Contrarianism and diversity

Hanania on Tetlock and the Taliban makes a point about the illusory nature of some expertise.

[Tetlock’s results] show that “expertise” as we understand it is largely fake. Should you listen to epidemiologists or economists when it comes to COVID-19? Conventional wisdom says “trust the experts.” The lesson of Tetlock (and the Afghanistan War), is that while you certainly shouldn’t be getting all your information from your uncle’s Facebook Wall, there is no reason to start with a strong prior that people with medical degrees know more than any intelligent person who honestly looks at the available data.

His examples about science community are neat. Then he draws a longer bow and makes some IMO less considered swipes at a weak-manned diversity argument which somewhat ruins the effect for me. Zeynep Tufekci gets at the problem that I think both people who talk about contrarianism and diversity would like to get at: Do the incentives, and especially the incentives in social structures, actually encourage the researchers towards truths, or towards collective fictions?

Sometimes, going against consensus is conflated with contrarianism. Contrarianism is juvenile, and misleads people. It’s not a good habit.

The opposite of contrarianism isn’t accepting elite consensus or being gullible.

Groupthink, especially when big interests are involved, is common. The job is to resist groupthink with facts, logic, work and a sense of duty to the public. History rewards that, not contrarianism.

To get the right lessons from why we fail—be it masks or airborne transmission or failing to regulate tech when we could or Iraq war—it’s key to study how that groupthink occurred. It’s a sociological process: vested interests arguing themselves into positions that benefit them.

Scott Alexander, Contrarians, Crackpots, and Consensus tries to break this idea open with an ontology.

I think a lot of things are getting obscured by the term “scientific establishment” or “scientific consensus”. Imagine a pyramid with the following levels from top to bottom:

FIRST, specialist researchers in a field…

SECOND, non-specialist researchers in a broader field…

THIRD, the organs and administrators of a field who help set guidelines…

FOURTH, science journalism, meaning everyone from the science reporters at the New York Times to the guys writing books with titles like The Antidepressant Wars to random bloggers…

ALSO FOURTH IN A DIFFERENT COLUMN OF THE PYRAMID BECAUSE THIS IS A HYBRID GREEK PYRAMID THAT HAS COLUMNS, “fieldworkers”, aka the professionals we charge with putting the research into practice. … FIFTH, the general public.

A lot of these issues make a lot more sense in terms of different theories going on at the same time on different levels of the pyramid. I get the impression that in the 1990s, the specialist researchers, the non-specialist researchers, and the organs and administrators were all pretty responsible about saying that the serotonin theory was just a theory and only represented one facet of the multifaceted disease of depression. Science journalists and prescribing psychiatrists were less responsible about this, and so the general public may well have ended up with an inaccurate picture.

Bright (2023):

Du Bois took quite the opposite route from trying to introduce lotteries, with their embrace of chance randomization. In fact, to a very considerable degree he centrally planned the sort of research his group would carry out so as to form an interlinking whole. Where the status quo system allows for competition between scientists to give funding out piecemeal to whoever seems best at a given moment, Du Bois’ work embodies the attitude that as far as possible our research activities should be coordinated, and not aimed at rewarding individual greatness but rather producing the best overall project. While ideas along these lines have not been totally without support in the history of philosophy of science (see e.g. Neurath 1946, Bernal 1949, Kummerfeld & Zollman 2015), it is safe to say the epistemic merits of this are relatively under-explored. Our brief examination of Du Bois’ plan will thus hopefully form a spur to generate more consideration of this sort of holistic line of action

3 Incoming

Figure 3

Smaldino and O’Connor (2020):

Why do bad methods persist in some academic disciplines, even when they have been clearly rejected in others? What factors allow good methodological advances to spread across disciplines? In this paper, we investigate some key features determining the success and failure of methodological spread between the sciences. We introduce a formal model that considers factors like methodological competence and reviewer bias towards one’s own methods. We show how self-preferential biases can protect poor methodology within scientific communities, and lack of reviewer competence can contribute to failures to adopt better methods. We then use a second model to further argue that input from outside disciplines, especially in the form of peer review and other credit assignment mechanisms, can help break down barriers to methodological improvement. This work therefore presents an underappreciated benefit of interdisciplinarity.

On the origin of psychological research practices, with special regard to self-reported nostril width:

when does a certain practice–e.g., a study design, a way to collect data, a particular statistical approach–”succeed” and start to dominate journals?

It must be capable of surviving a multi-stage selection procedure:

  1. Implementation must be sufficiently affordable so that researchers can actually give it a shot
  2. Once the authors have added it to a manuscript, it must be retained until submission
  3. The resulting manuscript must enter the peer-review process and survive it (without the implementation of the practice getting dropped on the way)
  4. The resulting publication needs to attract enough attention post-publication so that readers will feel inspired to implement it themselves, fueling the eternally turning wheel of Samsara publication-oriented science

The next few come from The Overedge Catalog: The Future of Research Organizations.

4 References

Agassi. 1974. The Logic of Scientific Inquiry.” Synthese.
Alon. 2009. How to Choose a Good Scientific Problem.” Molecular Cell.
Arbesman, and Christakis. 2011. Eurekometrics: Analyzing the Nature of Discovery.” PLoS Comput Biol.
Arvan, Bright, and Heesen. 2022. Jury Theorems for Peer Review.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
Azoulay, Fons-Rosen, and Zivin. 2015. Does Science Advance One Funeral at a Time? Working Paper 21788.
Bazzoli. 2022. Open Science and Epistemic Pluralism: A Tale of Many Perils and Some Opportunities.” Industrial and Organizational Psychology.
Bhattacharya, and Packalen. 2020. Stagnation and Scientific Incentives.” Working Paper 26752.
Board, and Meyer-ter-Vehn. 2021. Learning Dynamics in Social Networks.” Econometrica.
Bright. 2023. Du Bois on the Centralised Organisation of Science.” In Pluralising Philosophy’s Past.
Campante, Durante, and Tesei. 2022. Media and Social Capital.” Annual Review of Economics.
Chu, and Evans. 2021. Slowed Canonical Progress in Large Fields of Science.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences.
Dang, and Bright. 2021. Scientific Conclusions Need Not Be Accurate, Justified, or Believed by Their Authors.” Synthese.
Devezer, Nardin, Baumgaertner, et al. 2019. Scientific Discovery in a Model-Centric Framework: Reproducibility, Innovation, and Epistemic Diversity.” PLOS ONE.
Dubova, Moskvichev, and Zollman. 2022. Against Theory-Motivated Experimentation in Science.”
Farrow, and Moe. 2019. Rethinking the Role of the Academy: Cognitive Authority in the Age of Post-Truth.” Teaching in Higher Education.
Galesic, Barkoczi, Berdahl, et al. 2022. Beyond Collective Intelligence: Collective Adaptation.”
Gasparyan, Gerasimov, Voronov, et al. 2015. Rewarding Peer Reviewers: Maintaining the Integrity of Science Communication.” Journal of Korean Medical Science.
Greenberg. 2009. How Citation Distortions Create Unfounded Authority: Analysis of a Citation Network.” BMJ.
Healy. 2015. The Performativity of Networks.” European Journal of Sociology.
Heesen, and Bright. 2021. Is Peer Review a Good Idea? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
Hertz, Romand-Monnier, Kyriakopoulou, et al. 2016. Social influence protects collective decision making from equality bias.” Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and Performance.
Hirsch. 2013. Social Limits to Growth.” In Social Limits to Growth.
Hoelzemann, and Klein. 2021. Bandits in the Lab.” Quantitative Economics.
Ioannidis. 2005. Why Most Published Research Findings Are False. PLoS Medicine.
Jan. n.d. “Recognition and Reward System for Peer-Reviewers.”
Kearns, and Gardiner. 2011. The Care and Maintenance of Your Adviser.” Nature.
Lakatos. 1980. The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes: Volume 1 : Philosophical Papers.
McElreath, and Boyd. 2007. Mathematical Models of Social Evolution: A Guide for the Perplexed.
McElreath, and Smaldino. 2015. Replication, Communication, and the Population Dynamics of Scientific Discovery.” arXiv:1503.02780 [Stat].
Merrifield, and Saari. 2009. Telescope Time Without Tears: A Distributed Approach to Peer Review.” Astronomy & Geophysics.
Merton. 1968. The Matthew Effect in Science.” Science.
———. 1988. The Matthew Effect in Science, II: Cumulative Advantage and the Symbolism of Intellectual Property.” Isis.
Nissen, Magidson, Gross, et al. 2016. Publication Bias and the Canonization of False Facts.” arXiv:1609.00494 [Physics, Stat].
O’Connor. 2017. Evolving to Generalize: Trading Precision for Speed.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
O’Connor, and Bruner. 2019. Dynamics and Diversity in Epistemic Communities.” Erkenntnis.
O’Connor, and Weatherall. 2017. Scientific Polarization.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science.
———. 2019. The Misinformation Age: How False Beliefs Spread.
O’Connor, and Wu. 2021. How Should We Promote Transient Diversity in Science?
Osborne. 2022. Science Education in an Age of Misinformation.”
Rekdal. 2014. Academic Urban Legends.” Social Studies of Science.
Robbins. 1932. An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science.
Ross, Glennon, Murciano-Goroff, et al. 2022. Women Are Credited Less in Science Than Men.” Nature.
Rubin, and O’Connor. 2018. Discrimination and Collaboration in Science.” Philosophy of Science.
Rzhetsky, Foster, Foster, et al. 2015. Choosing Experiments to Accelerate Collective Discovery.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences.
Smaldino, and O’Connor. 2020. Interdisciplinarity Can Aid the Spread of Better Methods Between Scientific Communities.”
Smith, Sørensen, and Tian. 2021. Informational Herding, Optimal Experimentation, and Contrarianism.” The Review of Economic Studies.
Spranzi. 2004. Galileo and the Mountains of the Moon: Analogical Reasoning, Models and Metaphors in Scientific Discovery.” Journal of Cognition and Culture.
Stove. 1982. Popper and After: Four Modern Irrationalists.
Suppes. 2002. Representation and Invariance of Scientific Structures.
Thagard. 1993. “Societies of Minds: Science as Distributed Computing.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics.
———. 1994. “Mind, Society, and the Growth of Knowledge.” Philosophy of Science.
———. 1997. “Collaborative Knowledge.” Noûs.
———. 2005. “How to Be a Successful Scientist.” Scientific and Technological Thinking.
———. 2007. Coherence, Truth, and the Development of Scientific Knowledge.” Philosophy of Science.
Thagard, and Litt. 2008. “Models of Scientific Explanation.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Computational Psychology.
Thagard, and Zhu. 2003. “Acupuncture, Incommensurability, and Conceptual Change.” Intentional Conceptual Change.
The Importance of Frontier Knowledge for the Generation of Ideas.” 2018. CEPR.
Thurner, and Hanel. 2010. “Peer-Review in a World with Rational Scientists: Toward Selection of the Average.”
Valente, and Rogers. 1995. The Origins and Development of the Diffusion of Innovations Paradigm as an Example of Scientific Growth.” Science Communication.
Vazire. 2017. Our Obsession with Eminence Warps Research.” Nature News.
Wagenmakers, Sarafoglou, and Aczel. 2022. One Statistical Analysis Must Not Rule Them All.” Nature.
Weisbuch, Deffuant, Amblard, et al. 2002. Meet, Discuss, and Segregate! Complexity.
Weng, Flammini, Vespignani, et al. 2012. Competition Among Memes in a World with Limited Attention.” Scientific Reports.
Wible. 1998. Economics of Science.
Williams. 2022. The Marketplace of Rationalizations.” Economics & Philosophy.
Woodley, and Pratt. 2020. The CSCCE Community Participation Model – A Framework to Describe Member Engagement and Information Flow in STEM Communities.”
Wu, O’Connor, and Smaldino. 2022. The Cultural Evolution of Science.”
Yarkoni. 2019. The Generalizability Crisis.” Preprint.
Zimmer. 2020. How You Should Read Coronavirus Studies, or Any Science Paper.” The New York Times.